Abstract

The “Praecox Feeling” (PF) is a classical concept referring to a characteristic feeling of bizarreness experienced by a psychiatrist while encountering a person with schizophrenia. Although the PF used to be considered a core symptom of the schizophrenia spectrum, it fell into disuse since the spread of operationalized diagnostic methods (Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders/International Classification of Diseases systems). In contemporary research on schizophrenia, it remains largely unaddressed. This critical review investigates the evolution of the PF in historical and contemporary literature and presents an exhaustive overview of empirical evidence on its prevalence in clinical decision making, its reliability and validity. The review demonstrates that the PF is a real determinant of medical decision making in schizophrenia, although, without further research, there is not enough evidence to sustain its rehabilitation as a reliable and valid clinical criterion. PF-like experiences should not be opposed to any criteriological attitude in diagnosis and would be clinically useful if the conditions of descriptive precaution and rigorous epistemology are maintained. The aim of teaching clinical expertise is to transform this basic experience into a well-founded clinical judgment. Finally, the article discusses the possible relevance of the PF for basic science and clinical research according to a translational approach inspired by phenomenology.

Introduction

The “Praecox Feeling” (PF) is a classical concept referring to a characteristic feeling of unease or bizarreness experienced by a psychiatrist while interviewing a person with schizophrenia. PF used to be considered a core symptom of the schizophrenia spectrum, with high diagnostic specificity.1 In contemporary research it remains largely unaddressed. Considered too subjective or for some arbitrary, it is no longer present in current psychiatric definitions and viewed as inaccessible to psychopathological investigation and obsolete for pedagogy.2 This critical review investigates the evolution of the PF in historical and contemporary literature and presents an overview of empirical evidence on the prevalence of PF in clinical settings, its interrater reliability and validity. The article also discusses the possible role of the PF for basic science and clinical research according to translational approaches inspired by phenomenology. Finally, it proposes ideas for further investigation.

Classical Psychopathology and the History of PF

The notion of schizophrenia first occurred in Bleuler’s Dementia Praecox or the Group of Schizophrenias.3 Unlike Kraepelin, Bleuler grouped the disorders according to their common psychopathological determinant—their clinical core—and not their evolution. He spoke of the “intrapsychic Spaltung,” resulting in the release of the associations and detachment from reality (autism). This clinical core was more encompassing than the sum of independent clinical symptoms described by Kraepelin and was supposed to transpire through particular manifestations (Gestalt) of illness.4 Minkowski5 clarified later the idea of the direct recognition of this clinical core. He coined the term “diagnostic by penetration.” According to Minkowski, Bleuler did not go far enough in his conceptualization of schizophrenic autism.6 Focusing on mental contents, he missed the key link between a person and his/her world. The clinical core of schizophrenia consists of a “loss of vital contact with reality.” The patient loses “resonance” with the world, but not (as is the case of Bleuler’s autism) contact with the world. The diagnostic by penetration is precisely the ability to somehow passively recognize the clinical core in the motor behavior and contact with the patient.

We owe the expression the “Praecox Feeling” to Rümke, who defined it as a feeling of strangeness experienced by a clinician in the first minutes of the encounter with a patient. Rümke claimed that the diagnosis of schizophrenia is often reached through a passive and indescribable intuition. PF is less a symptom recognizable in the manner of object perception than a kind of atmospheric strangeness surrounding the encounter.7 It is described as the “the inability to come into contact with his/her personality as a whole.”8 It is sometimes experienced tacitly before the patient engages verbally. One “feels” it in his/her body posture, facial expression, the tone of the voice, motor behavior, and attitude. An attentive clinician intuitively feels these changes. Taken individually, the changes are insignificant, but as a whole they present the patient as “definitely un-understandable.” Rümke suggests that the PF could be explained by the fundamental inaccessibility of the patient to empathic understanding, no matter how well one comes to know his personal history and psychopathology.

Prior to Rümke, Jaspers has already emphasized the lack of empathic interaction and an inaccessibility to a first-person psychopathological understanding in schizophrenia.9,10 A similar idea was put forward later by Müller-Suur,11 according to whom the PF is primarily noticed by the clinician as an “indefinite un-understandability” initially experienced as the bizarreness of the affective exchange. Further on, the clinician searches for disconfirming evidence, which ultimately strengthens the validity of his/her initial impression. Through a process of critical reflection, the incomprehensibility of the patient that initially struck the psychiatrist becomes definite and can serve as a reliable clinical manifestation.

Although the PF is the most referenced notion, other close concepts can be found in literature: Wyrsch12 and Krauss13 have discussed “diagnosis through intuition,” and Tellenbach14 an “atmospheric diagnosis.” These authors have emphasized a close link between PF-like experience and specificity of diagnostic decision making in schizophrenia (see supplementary table S1).

Contemporary Psychopathology

The project of diagnostic operationalization originated in the late 1970s concerns about the reliability of psychiatric diagnosis that initially led to the formulation of Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Third Edition (DSM-III) in 1980.15,16 The ambition of this program was to enhance interrater reliability by the operationalization of diagnosis judgment and was heavily based on fully structured and standardized interview methods grounded in symptom checklists (ie, Structured Clinical Interview for DSM-IV [SCID-DSM-IV]). This “operational revolution” has profoundly modified the practice and teaching of psychiatric nosology worldwide. Collected third-person data were supposed to be context and observer independent.17,18 As a result, the PF fell into oblivion. It was now considered too “subjective” and incompatible with the project of scientific psychiatry. It was also stigmatized by the antipsychiatry movement as a symbol of the arbitrariness of psychiatric labeling.1

The consequence of these changes is that the PF remains largely unaddressed in contemporary psychopathology. The only remaining diagnostic criterion indirectly related to the notion of PF is “bizarre delusion” in DSM-III to DSM-IV, Text Revision. “Bizarre delusion,” however, was limited to delusional content and did not take into account the conditions of the intersubjective encounter.19,20 This criterion was removed from DSM-5.21 Nevertheless, as Nordgaard et al have shown, in the absence of universally accepted biomarkers, the validity of schizophrenia diagnosis is ultimately based on the accuracy of a psychiatric interview.22,23 This is why the epistemological exploration of the cognitive structure of diagnostic decision making is a fundamental domain of psychiatric science.

The PF experiential dimension remains inexplicable through the classic categories of behavioral description. To understand the ecological ways in which psychiatrists classify and comprehend illness, Schwartz and Wiggins24 have proposed to comprehend initial psychiatric diagnosis as a process of typification. They have argued that it is possible for a trained psychiatrist to recognize in the first minutes of the encounter with a patient his/her personality and situation as an “ideal type.”25 Typification is neither arbitrary nor intuitive. It is a cognitive process pertaining to basic perceptual processing that allows the identification of an object under conditions of incomplete information (as such, it is not limited to a psychiatric interview). It reveals the ideal–typical connections and not a set of virtually independent signs,26 and it gives order and meaning to the psychic states. The initial typification evolves along the interviewing process from a mainly tacit and elusive feeling to a more nuanced and specific impression. The scientific use of typifications requires that psychiatrists also doubt and reflect on their typifications and repeatedly test their interpretations by looking for additional components to prove or correct them.27 Typification processes are scientific only to the extent that they are based upon this dynamic circle of recognition and verification by the evidence-based criteria. For example, psychiatrists do not investigate hallucinations with all outpatients. Only because they have PF-like experiences, they conduct interviews exploring psychotic and hallucinatory incidents.

In spite of the absence of any reference in current psychiatric classifications, 2 issues in contemporary schizophrenia research may be associated with the PF: self-disorders (SDs) and intersubjectivity. First, growing phenomenologically oriented literature on basic (or minimal) SDs28,29 focuses on specific alterations of the structures of experiencing (such as comprehensively explored with Examination of Anomalous Self-Experience instrument30). SDs exhibit trait status and have been considered the clinical core in schizophrenia spectrum conditions. As Parnas1 argues, “it is not the question of a pathognomonic symptom but rather of a characteristic Gestalt.” Other authors have emphasized the clinical relevance of subtle psychopathological “pheno-phenotypes”31 such as SDs. Their neglect may lead to the oversimplification of clinical criteria, whereas research on biomarkers (eg, endophenotypes) needs stable and characteristic phenotypes.32 Another promising field of research relies on social cognition and intersubjectivity. Recent findings show disturbances among patients with schizophrenia regarding interpersonal sensory–motor synchronization,33 embodied cognition,34 intercorporeality,35 or enactivism.36 Fine intercorporeal adjustment and interaffectivity may constitute a basic background for intersubjectivity,37 and their disturbances in schizophrenia may lead to tacit interpersonal difficulties such as those involved in the PF.

Empirical Research

Only a few empirical studies have explored the PF. Nevertheless, there is evidence that the PF plays a role in diagnostic decision making in schizophrenia. The first type of evidence concerns the prevalence of self-declarations of PF-like determinants in diagnostic decision making. The second type of evidence concerns empirical evaluation of reliability and validity in experimental design studies (see supplementary table S2).

Three studies were conducted successively based on the same empirical design to explore the prevalence of the PF in clinical judgment processes. The first was conducted in West Germany in 1962, in the pre-DSM era38; the second in the United States in 1989, in the DSM-III era39; and the last in France, in the DSM-5 era.40 All have shown a high prevalence of the PF (85.9%, 82.8%, and 90.1%, respectively), exhibiting stability of the PF determinant in diagnostic decision making over time, despite the popularization of operationalized diagnostic tools since the 1980s. Paradoxically, the teaching of criteriological methods as cardinal diagnostic skills did not lead to any significant relegation of the PF from diagnostic decision making, contrary to what some have suggested.2,32,41

Regarding the experimental evidence of the reliability of the PF, a seminal study has shown that a deficient relationship with a patient is the second most reliable discriminator (reliability 0.86) in the diagnosis of schizophrenia, and is thus a legitimate foundation of diagnosis.42 A study on the specificity of schizophrenia symptoms (42 referenced symptoms) found a relatively low frequency of the PF (28%), whereas bizarreness was present in 43.3% in a population of patients with schizophrenia (n = 120) defined according to the DSM-III.43 A more recent study including 67 patients with acute positive psychotic symptoms measured the intensity of the PF in an experienced clinician during a few minutes long interview. Subsequently, a diagnostic assessment was performed according to standardized diagnostic classifications (International Classification of Diseases, Tenth Revision and DSM-IV) by an independent rater. The degree of correlation with the final diagnosis was high. The author found significantly higher PF intensity scores in subjects with a familial predisposition to schizophrenia.44 This is coherent with classic Gottesman and Shields’ twin studies.45 These results have been nuanced by a study46 exploring the reliability of the PF according to a different protocol: 102 admitted patients (37 with schizophrenia) were interviewed. This initial interview was observed by 5 psychiatrists who had never seen the patients before. It lasted 2 minutes and consisted of standard and nonspecific questions. Clinical observers independently assessed the intensity of the PF on the video record of the first interview. Then, a sixth psychiatrist examined the patients using the SCID-DSM-IV. This study found very inconsistent results between the 5 evaluators, all of which showed poor sensitivity and specificity. It is very likely that the contradictory results between the 2 studies can be related to experimental design: PF exhibited strong reliability when Grube encountered the enrolled patients face to face, whereas in Ungvari et al, the PF recognition was based on video watching, which could have led to crucial information being lost.

To date, there is no study investigating the validity of PF in schizophrenia according to validity criteria in the DSM system,47 despite some indirect evidence based on empirical research on the clinical encounter.48–50

Discussion

The review of literature shows that the PF is a real determinant of medical decision making in schizophrenia. Although there is insufficient evidence to sustain the rehabilitation of the PF as a reliable and valid clinical criterion consistent with the operational approach, a broader scientific approach is called for. PF should not be trivialized, as is sometimes the case, into a quick diagnosis.1,5 As opposed to a narrowly criteriological attitude in diagnosis, it is much more likely that physicians’ reasoning navigates constantly between (1) empathic, nondeclarative intuition and (2) criteriological verification of that intuition.1,22,24 Accordingly, we believe that the PF would be clinically useful if the conditions of descriptive precaution and rigorous epistemology are maintained. We, therefore, propose to distinguish the clinical manifestation of the PF from its underlying intersubjective phenomenon of common sense experience of bizarreness. The aim of teaching clinical expertise is to transform this basic and ubiquitous (not limited to health care situation) experience into critical and epistemologically well-founded clinical judgment.

Further investigation on the prevalence and reliability of PF must take into account the theoretical background of clinicians, professional clinical experience, and the context of practice. Furthermore, qualitative data on clinician subjective experience51 are needed for a better comprehension of diagnostic processes. In addition, attention must be paid to experimental design to better evaluate reliability by controlling the impact of the embodied dimension of interaction (direct clinical encounter vs verbatim vs video). Finally, there should be a strong emphasis on the multidimensional validity of the PF and its relation to symptomatic dimensions of schizophrenia (ultrahigh risk, clinical subtypes, severity, cognitive impairment with specific emphasis on social cognition, and embodied interaction), course of illness, recovery perspective, comorbidity, treatment response, altered neural functioning, and genetic risk factors.

In addition, novel experimental designs are called for to capture this nearly ineffable phenomenon: in our view, regarding the phenomenological hypothesis, the use of specific dedicated clinical evaluation of SDs is promising.31 Moreover, the PF can be investigated regarding recent neuroscientific research on social interaction with hyperscanning methods (which demonstrate that the coordination of humans engaged in social interaction is accompanied by the coordination of their brain activities52). As the PF is related to social interaction impairment, it may be related to abnormal brain synchronization. Present-day psychiatric neuroscientific research is challenged to play close attention to the particular nature of subjective experience in mental disorders and to develop techniques and interviewing methods adequate for this enterprise. The PF takes this ambition a step forward by addressing the complex problem of intersubjectivity as the epistemological basis of interview validity.

Acknowledgment

The authors have declared that there are no conflicts of interest in relation to the subject of this study.

References

1.

Parnas
J
.
A disappearing heritage: the clinical core of schizophrenia
.
Schizophr Bull
.
2011
;
37
:
1121
1130
.

2.

Andreasen
NC
.
DSM and the death of phenomenology in America: an example of unintended consequences
.
Schizophr Bull
.
2007
;
33
:
108
112
.

3.

Bleuler
E.
Dementia Praecox or the Group of Schizophrenias
.
Zinkin
J
., trans.
New York, NY
:
International Universities Press
;
1950
.

4.

Parnas
J
.
The core Gestalt of schizophrenia
.
World Psychiatry
.
2012
;
11
:
67
69
.

5.

Minkowski
E.
La Schizophrénie
.
Paris, France
:
Payot
;
1927
.

6.

Parnas
J
,
Bovet
P
,
Zahavi
D
.
Schizophrenic autism: clinical phenomenology and pathogenetic implications
.
World Psychiatry
.
2002
;
1
:
131
136
.

7.

Rümke
HC
.
Der klinische differenzierung innerhalb der gruppe der schizophrenien
.
Der Nervenarzt
.
1958
;
29
:
49
53
.

8.

Rümke
HC.
Studies en Voordrachten over Psychiatrie
.
Amsterdam, the Netherlands
:
Scheltema & Holkema
;
1948
.

9.

Jaspers
K.
General Psychopathology
.
Hoenig
J
,
Hamilton
MW
, trans.
London, UK
:
John Hopkins
;
1997

10.

Jaspers
K
.
The phenomenological approach in psychopathology
.
Br J Psychiatry
.
1968
;
114
:
1313
1323
.

11.

Müller-Suur
H
.
Das sogenannte praecoxgefuhl
.
Fortschr Neurol Psychiatr
.
1961
;
29
:
145
152
.

12.

Wyrsch
J
.
Über die Intuition bei der Erkennung des schizophrenen
.
Schweiz Med Wochenschr
.
1946
;
46
:
1173
1176
.

13.

Krauss
A
.
The significance of intuition for the diagnosis of schizophrenia
. In:
Maj
M
,
Sartorius
N
, eds.
Schizophrenia
.
Chichester, UK
:
John Wiley
;
1999
:
47
49
.

14.

Tellenbach
H.
Geschmack und Atmosphäre
.
Salzburg, Austria
:
Otto Müller Verlag
;
1968
.

15.

Aboraya
A
.
The reliability of psychiatric diagnoses: point-our psychiatric diagnoses are still unreliable
.
Psychiatry (Edgmont)
.
2007
;
4
:
22
25
.

16.

Sartorius
N
,
Shapiro
R
,
Kimura
M
,
Barrett
K
.
WHO International Pilot Study of Schizophrenia
.
Psychol Med
.
1972
;
2
:
422
425
.

17.

Robins
E
,
Guze
SB
.
Establishment of diagnostic validity in psychiatric illness: its application to schizophrenia
.
Am J Psychiatry
.
1970
;
126
:
983
987
.

18.

Spitzer
RL
.
Psychiatric diagnosis: are clinicians still necessary
?
Compr Psychiatry
.
1983
;
24
:
399
411
.

19.

Cermolacce
M
,
Sass
L
,
Parnas
J
.
What is bizarre in bizarre delusions? A critical review
.
Schizophr Bull
.
2010
;
36
:
667
679
.

20.

Sass
LA
,
Byrom
G
.
Self-disturbance and the bizarre: on incomprehensibility in schizophrenic delusions
.
Psychopathology
.
2015
;
48
:
293
300
.

21.

Tandon
R
,
Gaebel
W
,
Barch
DM
, et al. 
Definition and description of schizophrenia in the DSM-5
.
Schizophr Res
.
2013
;
150
:
3
10
.

22.

Nordgaard
J
,
Sass
LA
,
Parnas
J
.
The psychiatric interview: validity, structure, and subjectivity
.
Eur Arch Psychiatry Clin Neurosci
.
2013
;
263
:
353
364
.

23.

Phillips
J
,
Frances
A
,
Cerullo
MA
, et al. 
The six most essential questions in psychiatric diagnosis: a pluralogue part 3: issues of utility and alternative approaches in psychiatric diagnosis
.
Philos Ethics Humanit Med
.
2012
;
7
:
9
.

24.

Schwartz
MA
,
Wiggins
OP
.
Typifications. The first step for clinical diagnosis in psychiatry
.
J Nerv Ment Dis
.
1987
;
175
:
65
77
.

25.

Schwartz
MA
,
Wiggins
OP
.
Diagnosis and ideal types: a contribution to psychiatric classification
.
Compr Psychiatry
.
1987
;
28
:
277
291
.

26.

Fernandez
AV
.
Phenomenology, typification, and ideal types in psychiatric diagnosis and classification
. In:
Bluhm
R
, ed.
Knowing and Acting in Medicine
.
Lanham, MD
:
Rowman & Littlefield International
;
2016
:
39
58
.

27.

Moskalewicz
M
,
Schwartz
MA
,
Gozé
T
.
Phenomenology of intuitive judgment: praecox-feeling in the diagnosis of schizophrenia
.
AVANT
.
2018
;
9
:
63
74
.

28.

Sass
LA
,
Parnas
J
.
Schizophrenia, consciousness, and the self
.
Schizophr Bull
.
2003
;
29
:
427
444
.

29.

Parnas
J
,
Henriksen
MG
.
Disordered self in the schizophrenia spectrum: a clinical and research perspective
.
Harv Rev Psychiatry
.
2014
;
22
:
251
265
.

30.

Parnas
J
,
Møller
P
,
Kircher
T
, et al. 
EASE: Examination of Anomalous Self-Experience
.
Psychopathology
.
2005
;
38
:
236
258
.

31.

Stanghellini
G
,
Rossi
R
.
Pheno-phenotypes: a holistic approach to the psychopathology of schizophrenia
.
Curr Opin Psychiatry
.
2014
;
27
:
236
241
.

32.

Parnas
J
,
Sass
LA
,
Zahavi
D
.
Rediscovering psychopathology: the epistemology and phenomenology of the psychiatric object
.
Schizophr Bull
.
2013
;
39
:
270
277
.

33.

Berman
RA
,
Gotts
SJ
,
McAdams
HM
, et al. 
Disrupted sensorimotor and social–cognitive networks underlie symptoms in childhood-onset schizophrenia
.
Brain
.
2016
;
139
:
276
291
.

34.

Tschacher
W
,
Giersch
A
,
Friston
K
.
Embodiment and schizophrenia: a review of implications and applications
.
Schizophr Bull
.
2017
;
43
:
745
753
.

35.

Fuchs
T
.
Subjectivity and intersubjectivity in psychiatric diagnosis
.
Psychopathology
.
2010
;
43
:
268
274
.

36.

Varga
S
.
Vulnerability to psychosis, I-thou intersubjectivity and the praecox-feeling
.
Phenom Cogn Sci
.
2013
;
12
:
131
143
.

37.

Gozé
T
,
Grohmann
T
,
Naudin
J
,
Cermolacce
M
.
New insight into affectivity in schizophrenia: from the phenomenology of Marc Richir
.
Psychopathology
.
2017
;
50
:
401
407
.

38.

Irle
G
.
Das ‘Praecoxgefühl’ in der diagnostik der schizophrenie
.
Arch Psychiat Ztschr Ges Neurol
.
1962
;
203
:
385
406
.

39.

Sagi
GA
,
Schwartz
MA
.
The “Praecox Feeling” in the diagnosis of schizophrenia; a survey of Manhattan psychiatrists
.
Schizophr Research
.
1989
;
35
:
1
2
.

40.

Gozé
T
,
Moskalewicz
M
,
Schwartz
MA
, et al. 
Is “praecox feeling” a phenomenological fossil? A preliminary study on diagnostic decision making in schizophrenia
.
Schizophr Research
.
2018
. pii: S0920-9964(18)30487-0. doi:

41.

Maj
M
.
Critique of the DSM-IV operational diagnostic criteria for schizophrenia
.
Br J Psychiatry
.
1998
;
172
:
458
460
.

42.

Carpenter
WT
Jr,
Strauss
JS
,
Muleh
S
.
Are there pathognomonic symptoms in schizophrenia? An empiric investigation of Schneider’s first-rank symptoms
.
Arch Gen Psychiatry
.
1973
;
28
:
847
852
.

43.

Landmark
J
,
Merskey
H
,
Cernovsky
Z
,
Helmes
E
.
The positive triad of schizophrenic symptoms. Its statistical properties and its relationship to 13 traditional diagnostic systems
.
Br J Psychiatry
.
1990
;
156
:
388
394
.

44.

Grube
M
.
Towards an empirically based validation of intuitive diagnostic: Rümke’s “praecox feeling” across the schizophrenia spectrum: preliminary results
.
Psychopathology
.
2006
;
39
:
209
217
.

45.

Gottesman
II
,
Shields
J.
Schizophrenia and Genetics: A Twin Study Vantage Point
.
New York, NY
:
Academic Press
;
1972
.

46.

Ungvari
GS
,
Xiang
YT
,
Hong
Y
,
Leung
HC
,
Chiu
HF
.
Diagnosis of schizophrenia: reliability of an operationalized approach to “praecox-feeling”
.
Psychopathology
.
2010
;
43
:
292
299
.

47.

Micoulaud-Franchi
JA
,
Quiles
C
,
Batail
JM
, et al. 
Making psychiatric semiology great again: a semiologic, not nosologic challenge
.
Encephale
.
2018
;
44
:
343
353
. doi:

48.

Haker
H
,
Rössler
W
.
Empathy in schizophrenia: impaired resonance
.
Eur Arch Psychiatry Clin Neurosci
.
2009
;
259
:
352
361
.

49.

Dimic
S
,
Wildgrube
C
,
McCabe
R
,
Hassan
I
,
Barnes
TR
,
Priebe
S
.
Non-verbal behaviour of patients with schizophrenia in medical consultations—a comparison with depressed patients and association with symptom levels
.
Psychopathology
.
2010
;
43
:
216
222
.

50.

Lavelle
M
,
Healey
PG
,
McCabe
R
.
Nonverbal behavior during face-to-face social interaction in schizophrenia: a review
.
J Nerv Ment Dis
.
2014
;
202
:
47
54
.

51.

Gozé
T
,
Naudin
J
.
Discussing Rümke’s “Praecox Feeling” from the clinician’s experience of schizophrenic contact
.
Psicopsatologia Fenomenológica Contemporânea
.
2017
;
6
:
112
123
.

52.

Dumas
G
,
Nadel
J
,
Soussignan
R
,
Martinerie
J
,
Garnero
L
.
Inter-brain synchronization during social interaction
.
PLoS One
.
2010
;
5
:
e12166
.

This article is published and distributed under the terms of the Oxford University Press, Standard Journals Publication Model (https://academic.oup.com/journals/pages/open_access/funder_policies/chorus/standard_publication_model)