-
PDF
- Split View
-
Views
-
Cite
Cite
Pauli Murto, Juuso Välimäki, Affiliated Common Value Auctions with Costly Entry, The Review of Economic Studies, 2025;, rdaf015, https://doi.org/10.1093/restud/rdaf015
- Share Icon Share
Abstract
Many auctions and procurement contests entail non-trivial bidding costs, which makes the bidders’ participation decisions endogenous to the auction design. We analyse the effect of different auction rules on potential bidders’ incentives to participate. We focus on first-price auctions with affiliated common values and a large pool of potential bidders. Our main interest is on auctions where the realized number of bidders is unknown at the bidding stage. In contrast to the standard case, both participation and bidding decisions are often non-monotonic in the symmetric equilibrium of our model. The expected revenue to the seller is often higher in the auction where the realized number of participating bidders is not disclosed.
1 INTRODUCTION
In many markets, potential trading partners are dispersed and hard to identify ex ante. An important function of the trading mechanism is to bring the different parties together so that gains from trade can be realized. Procurement auctions are organized to attract bids from potential service providers. A start-up can signal its willingness to be bought by one of many established firms in the industry. A firm may advertise a vacancy to solicit applications from potential employees. These situations can be broadly understood as auctions, where the seller faces a non-trivial problem of attracting the buyers. How should competitive bidding be organized in such a case?
Entering an auction often entails significant costs. In addition to the opportunity cost of time and effort spent on being physically present at an auction site, the preparation of bids may be costly as a result of concerns for due diligence. If bids are prepared at a stage where the eventual number of participants is unknown, it is natural to consider the performance of auctions where the number of bidders is random and endogenous. We call such trading mechanisms informal auctions to distinguish from traditional formal auctions where the set of bidders is known at the time of placing the bids.1
Our model is particularly relevant for the analysis of procurement auctions where attracting sufficient participation is often problematic. In a recent paper, Kang and Miller (2021) document the scarcity of bidders for U.S. federal government procurement contracts, and they point out that many contracts have only a single relevant bidder. In our model with common values, optimal bidding changes radically if a bidder realizes that she is the only participant in the auction. In the informal auction format the bidders do not observe the presence of other bidders, and therefore this auction format makes it harder for them to extract the surplus from trade when no competing bidders are present.
We show that uncertainty in the number of actual bidders leads to new types of bidding equilibria and to new revenue results in single object auctions with affiliated common values. In particular, we demonstrate that informal first-price auctions perform better than their formal counterparts when entry costs are significant. In an affiliated auction, different auction rules result in different expected payoffs to bidders with different information at the bid preparation stage. With endogenous entry decisions, the type distributions of entering bidders reflect these payoff differences. We show that the selection induced by informal auctions generates more social surplus than the selection resulting from formal auctions. When a large number of potential entrants choose entry endogenously, the surplus is collected by the seller. This revenue result runs against the spirit of the linkage principle according to which the seller normally benefits from revealing information to the bidders.2
The previous literature on auctions with costly participation has analysed quite extensively formal auctions, where potential entrants make their entry decision in the first stage. In the second stage, all bidders who entered are informed of the realized number of participants as if they are arriving at an auction house. They then bid optimally in the ensuing auction.
In an informal auction, each bidder knows the equilibrium entry strategy of other potential participants but not the realized number of bidders at the time of choosing her bid. This auction format is meant to capture open selling procedures where interested bidders are invited to submit bids and the highest bidder wins and pays her own bid, as is typical in procurement. For independent private values, the usual mechanism design approach allows for the use of informal auctions, but the revenue equivalence theorem limits the significance of disclosing the realized number of bidders as a policy instrument.
We assume throughout that the true value of the good to the buyers is a binary random variable (the state variable of our model).3 We assume that trade is efficient in both states after accounting for the entry cost. Prior to any entry decisions, a large number of potential bidders have observed an affiliated private signal on the value of the object.
In Supplementary Appendix, we provide an alternative interpretation for the entry costs. We consider a large number of sellers who auction their (single indivisible) good to a large number of privately informed buyers. Each seller’s product has a binary common quality and the buyers receive a binary signal affiliated with the quality. In this market, the opportunity cost of choosing a different seller acts in the role of the entry cost in our main model.
Our main objective is to analyse how different auction formats influence selection, i.e. the realized distribution of types amongst the participating bidders. Affiliation is crucial for such effects. With statistically independent signals, the revenue equivalence theorem implies that all efficient auctions result in equilibria where only the most optimistic bidders (i.e. bidders with the highest posterior on the high state) participate and the seller’s expected revenue does not depend on the auction format. This is not true under affiliation.
Our first insight concerns efficient entry selection. We show that a utilitarian social planner restricted to symmetric entry strategies often induces entry by both the most optimistic and the most pessimistic bidders. With common values, the planner trades off duplicating the entry costs and missing out on profitable trades when no bidder enters. By affiliation, optimistic bidders are abundant if the value of the object is high, but they are relatively scarce if the value of the object is low. If entry costs are not too high, the optimal way to balance expected entry across the different states is by inducing entry from the most pessimistic bidders as well.
A qualitatively similar entry pattern occurs also in equilibrium. Affiliation implies that different bidders have different beliefs about the level of competition at the bidding stage. An individual bidder’s signal has therefore two separate effects. The direct effect of a high signal is that the bidder is more optimistic about the value of the object. The indirect effect is that the other bidders are more likely to be optimistic as well. Hence, a bidder with a high signal expects more aggressive bidding from other bidders, i.e. perceives the auction as more competitive.
These two effects are present in standard auctions as well, but entry costs highlight the second effect. Entry costs are sunk regardless of the outcome in the bidding stage. We show that this may lead to non-monotonic entry behaviour in the sense that both optimistic and pessimistic bidders enter and get the same ex ante expected payoff.4 We also show that uncertainty and in particular different beliefs about the number of opponents gives rise to non-monotonic bidding in the sense that participating bidders with high signal sometimes lose in informal auctions to bidders with lower signals.
Affiliated auctions with uncertain numbers of bidders are hard to analyse precisely because equilibria in monotone strategies may fail to exist.5 Without monotonicity, it is not clear how one should proceed in the standard affiliated model with a continuum of signals as in Milgrom and Weber (1982). In fact, Lauermann and Speit (2023) show that with exogenous entry rates, equilibria may fail to exist altogether. In order to make progress, we assume that the signals are drawn from a finite set and they are independent across the potential bidders conditional on the true value of the object.
We model the auction as a Poisson game where the type of each potential player is affiliated with the value of the object. The number of entrants of each type is drawn from a Poisson distribution with a parameter that depends on the true binary value of the object and an endogenously determined entry rate for each type. An equilibrium of this game is a distribution of entrants and bids such that all entrants can cover their cost by their expected profit and no potential bidder of any type can make a strictly positive profit by entering.
One key feature of our equilibrium construction is that only extreme bidder types enter in equilibrium. We base our analysis on the bidders’ expected payoffs conditional on the state. With a binary state and affiliated signals, the beliefs of the potential bidders on the state of the world are monotone in their signals. In equilibrium, the expected payoff at the auction stage must equal the entry cost for any type entering at a positive rate. If the expected payoffs in the two states differ at a fixed bid, only those potential bidders that assign the highest probability to the more favourable state make that bid. This implies that only bidders with the most extreme beliefs enter in equilibrium, and we may restrict attention to models with only two bidder types present at the bidding stage. We establish the existence and uniqueness of a symmetric equilibrium bid distribution in the overall game and we compute the equilibrium entry rates and equilibrium bids for our model.6
We get our strongest results when the entry cost is relatively high (so that the expected number of entrants is relatively low), and when signals are strongly affiliated. The low participation rate observed in Kang and Miller (2021) could indicate high bidding costs for typical procurement auctions.7 In this case, placing a zero bid is in the support of the symmetric equilibrium bid distribution for both entering types. With atomless bidding strategies, a zero bid wins only if there are no other bidders. At this bid, the private benefit coincides with the planner’s benefit from inducing additional entry when restricted to symmetric strategies. This means that the symmetric equilibrium entry rates maximize utilitarian welfare in the class of symmetric entry strategies. Since we have a large number of potential bidders, their expected payoff net of entry costs must be zero and as a result the seller receives the maximal symmetric surplus as her expected revenue. For these parameter values, we see then that the informal auction is a revenue maximizing mechanism in the class of all symmetric mechanisms.
We also show that when entry in the informal auction differs from the planner’s solution, a relatively simple change to the auction rules restores the efficiency. This requires a suitable combination of two separate instruments. By setting an entry fee and by allowing negative bids up to a given level, the seller can, in principle, induce efficient equilibrium entry rates and collect the entire expected social surplus in revenues. In the main body of the article, we normalize the seller’s valuation of the product at zero so that negative bids can be interpreted as (positive) bids below the seller’s valuation. In a procurement auction, this corresponds to allowing bids above the value of the service to the organizer of the auction. An important caveat is that when bids below the sellers valuation are possible, the seller must be able to commit ex ante to accepting them in case no better offers are available.8
1.1 Related literature
Lauermann and Wolinsky (2017) analyse a model where the seller invites bidders to an auction, and Lauermann and Wolinsky (2016) analyse a model of sequential search for trading partners in a similar setting. Our model is based on a different premise on the costs of identifying potential trading partners. If such costs are prohibitive, the seller must rely on trading partners’ self selection into the mechanism. This leads us to analyse voluntary endogenous entry into auctions in a setting that is otherwise quite close to Lauermann and Wolinsky (2017). Atakan and Ekmekci (2021) analyses a related model, where the choice between competing auctions creates an opportunity cost of participating, but their focus is on information aggregation as the numbers of bidders and objects grow large.
Endogenous entry into auctions has been modelled in two separate frameworks. In the first, entry decisions are taken at an ex ante stage where all bidders are identical. Potential bidders learn their private information only upon paying the entry cost. Hence these models can be thought of as games with endogenous information acquisition.9 French and McCormick (1984) give the first analysis of an auction with an entry fee in the IPV case. Harstad (1990) and Levin and Smith (1994) analyse the affiliated interdependent values case. These papers show that due to business stealing, entry is excessive relative to social optimum. They also show that formal second-price auctions dominate the formal first-price auction in terms of expected revenue. Informal auctions are thus not covered in these papers.
In the other strand, bidders decide on entry only after knowing their own signals. Samuleson (1985) and Stegeman (1996) are early papers in the independent private values setting where this question has been taken up. More recently, Bhattacharya et al. (2014) and Sweeting and Bhattacharya (2015) analyse IPV models with selective entry where entry decisions are conditioned on private information on the true valuation.
Matthews (1987) analyses a first-price auction with affiliated private values with an exogenously given random number of participants. He proves a reverse linkage principle result that implies higher revenues for the seller if the realized number of bidders is kept secret. In contrast to our article, Matthews (1987) assumes monotonicity of best responses in signals and in the number of bidders (when disclosed) but does not characterize when equilibria in such strategies exist.10 Pekec and Tsetlin (2008) provide an example of a common value auction where informal first-price auction results in a higher expected revenue than an informal second-price auction. The distribution of the bidders in that paper is somewhat extreme and not derived from entry decisions. Lauermann and Speit (2023) demonstrate the non-existence of equilibria in a binary common values first-price auction with an exogenously given random number of bidders. They analyse the case where the value of the good is zero in the low state and based on this assumption they show that individual best responses are monotone in bidders’ signals. If the value is strictly positive in both states, this monotonicity may fail.
Since we concentrate on symmetric equilibria of a game with a large number of potential entrants, our model has some similarities to the urn-ball models of matching. Similar to those models, our insistence on symmetric equilibria can be seen as a way of capturing a friction in the market that precludes coordinated asymmetric decisions. A recent example of such models is Kim and Kircher (2015) that studies matching with private values uncertainty. This approach has also been used in Jehiel and Lamy (2015) in a procurement auction setting with private (asymmetric) values. These models do not consider the case of common values.
The article is structured as follows. Section 2 presents the main model. Section 3 goes through some preliminary results to set the stage for our main results. Section 4 characterizes the unique equilibrium in both informal and formal auction models. Section 5 compares the expected revenues across different auction formats and Section 6 discusses the modelling assumptions in this article. All proofs omitted from the main text are in the Appendix.
2 MODEL
A seller has a single indivisible object for sale. The value of the object, , is common to all potential bidders and determined by a binary random variable with realizations . We denote the prior probability of the event by q. There is a pool of potential bidders who choose whether or not to enter the auction. The cost of entering and making a bid is for an individual bidder.11 We assume that and normalize the value to the seller at zero. This implies that is the social surplus from trading in state ω.
Each potential bidder observes a signal with realizations in . The common conditional distribution of signals in state is denoted by:
We label the signals so that they satisfy strict monotone likelihood ratio property: is increasing in m. We denote by the posterior belief on state after seeing signal :
We model the number of potential bidders by a Poisson random variable with an exogenously given parameter λ, where we assume that is large in comparison to .12 The endogenously determined entry rate of type m entrants is denoted by , where is the entry probability for potential entrants of type m. Given the affiliated signal structure, the realized number of participants of type m is then given by a Poisson random variable with parameter that depends on and the exogenously given signal distribution (1) across the two states.
In the informal auction, participating bidders place their bids before learning the realized number of other participating bidders. A bidder with the highest bid wins and pays her own bid.13 A symmetric strategy profile is a pair , where is a distribution on positive bids for each type of participating bidders and is a vector of entry rates. By a symmetric equilibrium of the informal auction, we mean a pair , such that no bid gives an expected payoff strictly above c for any bidder type. If , then the expected payoff from all bids in the support of the bid distribution of type m is exactly c.
We will later compare the informal auction with a formal (first-price) auction where the bidders learn the number of competing bidders before placing their bids. In the formal auction, the entry strategy is as above, but the bidding strategy conditions on the realized number of participating bidders. As with the informal auction, a bidder with the highest bid wins and pays her own bid.
In the Supplementary Appendix, we show that our main results extend to a market setting consisting of a large number of sellers and a large number of bidders. Each seller is endowed with a single indivisible good of uncertain common quality, and each buyer (with unit demand) receives conditionally independent signals from each seller and then choose which type of seller (in terms of the signal received) to approach.14 This gives us an alternative interpretation of the common participation cost c as an opportunity cost of participating in a different auction. We show that a low (respectively high) entry cost c in our main model corresponds to a market with a high (respectively low) ratio of buyers to sellers.
3 PRELIMINARY ANALYSIS OF THE INFORMAL AUCTION
In this section, we derive some preliminary results. In Section 3.1, we derive the optimal entry profile for a social planner restricted to anonymous strategies. We show that the optimum in this benchmark can be obtained by profiles where only bidders with signals or enter with positive probability. In Section 3.2, we show that also equilibrium entry profiles feature only the two types and . Finally, in Section 3.3, we fix an exogenous entry profile by the extreme types and derive the corresponding atomless bidding equilibrium. We use these results in the next section to characterize the full equilibrium with endogenous entry.
3.1 Symmetric planner’s optimum
The social planner chooses entry rates to maximize the expected gain from allocating the object net of expected entry costs. The expected total surplus depends only on the total expected number of entrants in each state ω:
Any with is feasible with positive entry rates and can be achieved with entry by extreme types only. If at the unconstrained optimum , then only the highest type enters at a strictly positive rate.15 If two or more types enter with a strictly positive rate, then the expected social benefit from added entry must coincide with the cost of entry in both states.16
Proposition 1 below shows that such a solution exists whenever the entry cost c is low enough or signals are strongly affiliated in the sense that is large enough. Furthermore, an optimal solution can be obtained at an extremal entry rate vector π such that for .
3.2 Entry by extreme types
To analyse the entry incentives of different types, it is useful to consider payoffs conditional on state. We denote by the expected equilbrium rent at the auction stage in state ω from submitting bid p:
where is c.d.f. of the bid distribution of type . Since this rent is conditional on the state, bidders of all types agree on .
In prior work on auctions with exogenous uncertainty on the number of bidders, Lauermann and Wolinsky (2017) demonstrate the possibility of pooling bids, i.e. atoms in the bid distribution. Our first result shows that with endogenous entry decisions, pooling is not possible.
There are no atoms in the bidding distribution b of a symmetric equilibrium .
We consider next the types of bidders that can enter in an equilibrium with atomless bidding strategies. For each p, there are three possibilities: either (i) , (ii) or (iii) . All types of bidders are indifferent between entering and submitting a bid p in case i). In case (ii), only type can make bid p in equilibrium with interior entry probabilities. If , , makes the bid, her expected payoff at the bidding stage is , and she must earn at least c to be willing to enter and bid p. But since , type will get strictly more than c by entering and bidding p, which cannot be an equilibrium. Similarly in Case (iii), only type can enter in equilibrium.
Our equilibrium construction shows that all the Cases (i)–(iii) are possible, but the bid distribution is fully pinned down by the parameters of the bidders that bid in Cases (ii) and (iii). The only remaining indeterminacy concerns the exact composition of bidders that make bids where Case (i) holds. But the requirement that the expected payoffs be equalized across the two states determines the aggregate distributions of bids for each state in a manner analogous to the payoff equalization across the two states in the planner’s problem. As in the planner’s case, these aggregate distributions can be generated with positive entry by types and . We formalize this discussion in the following Lemma:
Let denote an equilibrium of a reduced model, where only types exist. Then remains an equilibrium of the full model that allows entry by all types . Moreover, the equilibrium distribution of bids (and therefore also the expected revenue) in any other equilibrium of the full model coincides with the equilibrium distribution of bids in an equilibrium of the reduced model.
3.3 Bidding equilibrium of the two-type model
Based on Lemmas 1 and 2, we can restrict our attention to atomless bidding equilibria of a model with binary bidder types where labels l and h correspond to the extreme types and of the full model, respectively. In this subsection, we characterize further the set of possible bidding equilibria b. The full equilibrium with endogenous entry will be analysed in the next section.
Recall that the number of bidders with signal θ in state ω is a Poisson random variable with parameter . With affiliated signals, and . This in turn implies that and for any entry profile . The expected payoff from a bid p to a bidder of type θ when the other players bid according to the profile is:
A symmetric bidding equilibrium for entry rate profile π is a bid profile such that for all supp p maximizes . Using this property and the functional form of , we can pin down some key properties of a bidding equilibrium. Lemma 3 below shows that depending on the entry rate profile, we are in one of two qualitatively distinct cases. The first case is just a discrete type version of a standard monotonic equilibrium: the higher type always bids higher than the low type. The second case is novel to our model and shows that the bidding equilibrium may fail to be monotonic. The bid supports overlap and hence a low type wins against a high type with a positive probability.
Bid supports overlap if the value of the object does not differ too much across the two states or if the signals are sufficiently correlated. In the extreme case, where the signals are perfectly correlated, the two extreme types randomize on an interval starting at .
To get an intuition for why 0 must be in the supports of both types when inequality (3) holds, assume for a moment that the supports do not overlap and let be the low-type bidders’ support. The proof of Lemma 3 shows that if (3) holds and the low type is indifferent between bidding 0 and , then the high type has a strict incentive to bid 0 rather than . Intuitively, under (3) the probability that some low-type bidders are present is so much higher in state 0 than in state 1 that a low-type bidder has a higher incentive to raise one’s bid above other potential low-type bidders than a high-type bidder.
It should be emphasized that so far we have not proven the existence of an equilibrium in our model. The lemmas above should therefore be understood as a characterization of a candidate for an equilibrium bidding strategy. Lauermann and Speit (2023) show that a bidding equilibrium may fail to exist in a first-price auction with an exogenously given type distribution. This possibility is present in our model with exogenous entry as well.17 In the next section, we show that with endogenous entry, our model has always a unique symmetric bidding equilibrium and so the characterization in Lemma 3 is valid.
4 EQUILIBRIUM WITH ENDOGENOUS ENTRY
In this section, we consider the equilibrium entry rates in informal and formal auctions. We analyse their properties through a comparison with the symmetric social planner’s solution. Therefore, we set the stage in Section 4.1 by explaining the distinction between private and social entry incentives. In Section 4.2, we analyse the equilibrium of the informal auction and in Section 4.3, we analyse the equilibrium of the formal auction.
4.1 Private and social incentives for entry
It is helpful to start by considering a hypothetical game where the object is given for free to the entrant if there is a single entrant. With two or more entrants the object is withdrawn from the market but the entrants have to pay the entry cost. Denote by the expected payoff to a bidder of type at the auction stage with the symmetric entry profile :
Any such that in the above equations guarantees that every potential entrant is indifferent between entering and staying out. Note also that in this hypothetical situation each entrant gets exactly her marginal contribution to the social welfare as her payoff. Since the value of the object is common to all the players, an entrant contributes to the total surplus if and only if she is the only entrant. Since the object is given for free to the sole entrant, her private benefit equals her marginal contribution and the private value of entry coincides with the social value of entry. We show below that our different auction formats give (at least weakly) too high entry incentives for the high types. Quantifying this excessive entry incentive across different auction formats gives us our revenue comparisons.
In Figure 1, we illustrate the social optimum in the case with interior entry probabilities by drawing in the plane the planner’s reaction curves:
where is the expected total surplus at entry profile :
The social optimum is at the intersection of these curves. These curves are also the indifference contours and for a potential entrant of type h and l, respectively, who gets her marginal contribution as expected payoff.

Auctions often give an additional reward to high type entrants on top of their social contribution. This distorts equilibrium entry rates from socially optimal levels. Since bidding zero is in the support of the low type bidders by Lemma 3, their equilibrium entry incentives coincide with the planner’s incentives conditional on the entry rate of the high types.18 As a result, their equilibrium reaction curve coincides with the planner’s reaction curve and hence any equilibrium entry profile must be on the planner’s reaction curve for the low type. For our revenue comparisons, it is therefore useful to analyse how movements along that curve change the total surplus.
We denote by the total surplus when low types react optimally to :
The following lemma shows that is single peaked in with its peak at . This is illustrated in Figure 1 by the arrows along that point towards increasing social surplus. Based on this lemma, we can compare auction formats simply by analysing how far they distort the entry rate of the high type away from the social optimum.
Notice that by Proposition 1 the planner’s solution has only when . If , there is no entry by the low type in the planner’s solution and this must be the case also in equilibrium, irrespective of whether the auction is formal or informal.19 Consequently, as all the entering bidders have observed a high signal, the expected payoff to the entering bidders is given by the probability that no other bidder entered times the expected value of the object conditional on that event.20 Since the updated belief of a high type bidder on is given by , equating the expected benefit from entry to the cost of entry gives:
which coincides with the planner’s optimality condition. Hence, the symmetric equilibrium entry profile in both auction formats coincides with the planner’s optimal solution. Since the bidders expected payoff is zero, the seller collects the entire expected social surplus in expected revenues and hence both auction formats are also revenue maximizing within the class of symmetric mechanisms (where we require symmetry at the entry stage as well as at the bidding stage):
If , then only the high type enters in the planner’s solution and both auction formats are efficient and hence revenue equivalent.
4.2 Entry equilibrium in informal auctions
We now consider the entry equilibrium in the more interesting case , where the planner’s solution induces entry by both types. We use the three lemmas of the previous section to narrow down the set of possible equilibria in various ways. By Lemma 1, there are no symmetric equilibria with pooling bids, so we can concentrate on atomless bidding strategies. By Lemma 2 we can concentrate on the lowest and highest type of potential entrants. Finally, Lemma 3 further narrows down the form of bidding strategies to two distinct cases. In this section, we show the existence of a unique equilibrium consistent with these Lemmas.
We denote by the expected payoff of a bidder with type θ at the bidding stage of the informal first-price auction for given entry rates . We show that there is a unique pair such that .
In addition to the uniqueness, the proposition below contains a qualitative statement about the equilibrium. Each low type entrant gets a payoff in the bidding stage that is exactly equal to her social contribution:
which means that equilibrium entry profile must be located along the planner’s reaction curve . High type bidders may get a higher payoff. In order to dissipate the excess rent of the high types, we must have . As a result, the equilibrium entry rate must be (weakly) too high for the high type and (weakly) too low for the low type in comparison to the planner’s optimum.
4.3 Entry equilibrium in formal auctions
We showed in Lemma 2 above that for informal auctions, we can restrict our analysis to the two-type model. The same is true for formal auctions. In fact, we can show that the bidding equilibria of formal auctions are simpler than in the informal auction in the sense that for all bid levels, either the lowest or the highest type has a strict advantage over any intermediate type. This implies that the intermediate types can never break even in equilibrium and so there cannot be any equilibria where intermediate types enter with positive rate.
Let denote the vector of entry rates by different types in an equilibrium of the formal auction. Then , i.e. only types and may enter with a strictly positive rate.
Since only two types enter in equilibrium, we can use the following characterization of the unique symmetric bidding equilibrium in formal auctions taken from Chi et al. (2019).
High type bidders earn a higher private benefit in the bidding stage than their contribution to the social surplus. To see this, recall that in a model with common values additional entry is socially valuable only if no other bidder participates in the auction. In the formal auction high type bidders receive the social benefit (i.e. object for free if ), but she also an extra information rent when bidding against low type bidders when . By bidding , a high type wins against low types, and her payment is lower than her expectation of the value of the object given her signal. As a result, equilibrium entry is socially excessive in formal auctions.
Given the bidding equilibrium characterized above we can prove the existence and uniqueness of symmetric equilibria for formal auctions with endogenous entry. Proposition 3 below mirrors Proposition 2 for informal auctions. The main qualitative difference is that in formal auctions, equilibrium entry rates are always distorted away from the socially optimal levels as long as entry cost is low enough to induce entry by both types.
Let . The formal first-price auction has a unique symmetric equilibrium where only the extreme types enter with strictly positive rate. The equilibrium entry rates by the highest and lowest types, respectively, satisfy and .
Note that if , then the low type does not enter and Remark 1 applies.
5 REVENUE COMPARISONS
5.1 Formal versus informal auctions
We compare next the expected equilibrium revenues of informal and formal auctions when multiple types of bidders enter in equilibrium, i.e. when . Our first result shows that when the affiliation is strong and the entry cost is sufficiently large, the informal auction gives the entire (symmetric) social surplus to the seller in expected revenues. To see when this happens, recall from Lemma 3 that the bid supports of both type of bidders must contain 0 whenever
The left-hand side is decreasing in , and approaches when . This ratio measures the difference across the states of the probability of observing a low signal, and reflects the divergence in the beliefs of different bidder types on the degree of competition at the bidding stage. Whenever this ratio is larger than the ratio of payoffs across the states, a sufficiently high entry cost will result in a low entry rate for the low type bidders. In this case, a zero bid must be in the high-type bidders’ support and they get no rent on top of their contribution to the social welfare in the informal auction. As a result, the informal first price auction maximizes the seller’s expected revenue in the class of all symmetric mechanisms.
In contrast, in formal auctions the high-type will always get an information rent that strictly exceeds her social contribution and entry rates are distorted away from social optimum. This establishes the strict superiority of the informal first price auction.
When (5) does not hold and/or entry cost is very low, the revenue comparison is less straightforward. In this case, the informal auction also induces too much entry by the high types and the distortions across the two formats must be compared. We show below that as long as the entry cost is substantial enough, the superiority of the informal auction continues to hold, but a more elaborate argument is needed. The key to understanding this is the linkage principle with uncertainty in the number of competing bidders.
The linkage principle by Milgrom and Weber (1982) says that the expected revenue increases if an auction format induces a positive linkage between a bidder’s own signal and her expected payment, conditional on winning the auction. As explained by Milgrom and Weber (1982), one implication of this is that the expected price increases if public information reinforces the linkage between bidders’ signals and their expected payments. However, Matthews (1987) observes that in an auction with affiliated private values and exogenous random participation, revealing the number of bidders creates a negative linkage between a bidder’s own signal and her expected payment. Therefore, revealing the number of bidders decreases the seller’s expected revenue. Both Milgrom and Weber (1982) and Matthews (1987) assume that the type distribution of the bidders is independent of the auction format. We discuss below how the insights from the linkage principle extend to our setting with endogenous participation.
In the informal auction, one’s own signal has no effect on expected payment conditional on winning at the submitted bid. In the formal auction, in contrast, one’s own signal influences the expected payment through its effect on the distribution of the number of bidders n conditional on winning. In a formal auction, n is revealed before the bidding stage and the equilibrium bid depends on n. Recall from Lemma 6 that for any realized n, low types pool at and the high types mix over interval . To isolate the linkage of own signal to expected payment in a model with discrete types and mixed strategies requires some care. Consider a bidding strategy where the bidder wins against low types but loses against all high types, i.e. bid with vanishingly small. Since this bidding strategy is essentially optimal for both the low and high type, we can use it to isolate the linkage between own signal and expected payment.21 The expected payment conditional on winning with that strategy is just the expectation of over n conditional on no high types entering, where we define since a solitary bidder bids zero.
By affiliation, a high type expects a smaller number of low type bidders and hence a lower n conditional on no high types. If were decreasing in n, the linkage principle would work in the normal way: a high type bidder expects to pay more than the low type. By affiliation, is indeed decreasing in n for since the posterior on is decreasing in the number of low type bidders. Notice, however, that . This breaks the monotonicity of . A high type bidder evaluates the probability that there are no low type bidders present to be higher than a low type bidder. This reduces the expected payment of the high type relative to the low type. If the entry rate of the low type bidders is small enough, this prospect of facing no competition dominates and makes the linkage between signal and expected payment negative.22 If the entry rate of the low type is very high, we are no longer able to say which linkage effect dominates.
We conclude that whenever the entry rate of the low type bidders is sufficiently low, revealing the number of bidders introduces a negative linkage between a bidder’s signal and her expected payment. If entry rates are fixed, this means that the high type bidder’s expected rent is higher in the formal auction than in the informal auction. But when entry rates are endogenous, this further implies that the entry incentive of the high-type is distorted more in the formal than in the informal auction. Translated into the exogenous parameters of the model, this implies that whenever entry cost is high enough, the informal first-price auction dominates formal first-price auction in terms of expected revenue.
There is a , such that for , informal first-price auction generates a strictly higher expected revenue than formal auctions.
5.2 Entry fees, reserve prices, and posted prices
One can ask if the seller can increase her expected revenue by other auction design features such as entry fees or reserve prices. If the conditions in Proposition 4 hold, then the informal auction induces the highest possible total surplus and gives this entirely to the seller. In that case it is clear that no symmetric mechanism can improve the expected revenue.
If the informal auction is inefficient, then there is a distortion in entry rates that could potentially be reduced or even eliminated. The distortion results from the positive equilibrium rent of the high-type bidders. Hence it would be desirable to find an instrument that penalizes high types but not the low types.
An entry fee is an instrument that penalizes both types equally. As a result, adding a small entry fee modifies the entry incentive of the high types in the intended direction, but at the same time affects the low types in the wrong direction. An argument based on the envelope theorem suggests that a small entry fee could marginally increase revenue. To see this, note that in equilibrium, entry by the low types is socially optimal conditional on the entry rate of the high types. Therefore, a slight change in the low type entry rate will not have a first-order effect on the total surplus. In contrast, the high type entry rate is already distorted away from social optimum and therefore a small change has a first-order effect in total surplus and revenue.
To improve entry selection further one would need to compensate for the penalizing effect of the entry fee to the low types with another instrument. In the main part of our article, we have set the minimum bid equal to the value of the object to the seller. Suppose that the seller can commit to accepting bids below v (i.e. negative bids in the main analysis). Since lowering the minimum bid will be particularly beneficial to a bidder that happens to be alone in the market, and since such a scenario is more likely from the point of view of a low type bidder, this instrument indeed rewards more the low types than the high types. By suitably combining these two instruments, an entry fee and a reduced minimum bid, we can indeed modify the entry incentives of both types of bidders to achieve socially optimal entry selection. We show in the proposition below that this works both in the context of informal and formal auctions.
Notice that in the procurement context, lowering the minimum bid below the seller’s value should be interpreted as increasing the maximum bid above the auctioneer’s value for the service. We should point out that committing to accepting bids below v (or above v in the procurement context) may be very hard in practice. If the seller can make shill bids, she has always an incentive to bid v at the auction stage. If the potential participants anticipate this, entry rates will not respond as intended. In order to manipulate the equilibrium entry rates, the auctioneer must find a way to credibly commit not to make shill bids.
We also show that the same expected revenue can be realized using a posted price together with an entry fee. In this case, the optimal posted price is negative, and the seller uses symmetric rationing between the participating buyers. By charging negative prices, the seller rewards winning the object, but by posting a strictly positive participation fees, she punishes entry.
It should be noted that setting optimal minimum bids, posted prices, and participation fees requires that the auctioneer has full knowledge of the distribution of the valuations. In other words, this is not detail free in the same way as the informal first-price auction. In this mechanism, the seller also must commit to not using shill buyers.
A suitably chosen combination of a positive entry fee and a negative minimum bid yields an equilibrium with socially optimal entry profile . The same entry rates can be induced by a negative posted price , symmetric randomization between participating bidders, and an entry fee .
6 DISCUSSION
6.1 Auctions versus procurement
Our model is written as an auction where the seller has a known valuation of zero for the object that she is selling. This means that the values and should be interpreted as gains from trade in the two states. The lower bound for bids is then set at the value of the object to the seller.
The model can also be interpreted as a reverse auction as typically used in procurement. In this case, the auctioneer has a known valuation of v for a service and the bidders face common values uncertainty regarding the cost of providing it. In a first-price reverse auction, a bidder with the lowest bid wins the auction and receives her bid as a payment from the auctioneer. The types correspond to conditionally i.i.d. signals on the cost of provision. The restriction to non-negative bids in the auction corresponds to an upper bound of v on the bids in procurement.
6.2 Second-price auctions
We view the first-price auction format as the natural model to describe bidding contests in situations where the set of bidders is unknown. Nevertheless, one may ask how our results would be affected if we adopt the second-price payment rule.
In Chi et al. (2019), we show that with two bidder types, the formal first-price and formal second price auction generate the same expected revenue. This implies that with endogenous entry, entry rates and therefore also equilibrium revenues coincide in the two formal auctions. We should note that this equivalence relies on our finding that only two types of bidders are present in the bidding stage, as established in Lemma 5. We know from Milgrom and Weber (1982) that such equivalence would not hold if the participating bidders draw their types from a more general signal space.
In our previous working paper, we also analysed the informal second-price auction. As such, this format is particularly vulnerable to manipulation by shill bids. A closely related format would be an informal ascending clock auction where the price increases until only the winning bidder remains and no further information is provided during the auction.
The main difficulty for that analysis arises from the multiplicity of symmetric bidding equilibria. Regardless of how the equilibrium is selected, the high type bidders always get a positive information rent on top of their social contribution. This distorts their entry rates above the symmetric social optimum. If the informal first-price auction is efficient, it raises a higher revenue than the informal second-price auction.
If we select the bidder optimal equilibrium in the bidding stage, we get an unambiguous revenue ranking between the two informal auction formats: the informal first-price auction raises a higher revenue than the informal second price auction.
6.3 Asymmetric equilibria and participation by invitation
In models with entry costs, one often finds that asymmetric equilibrium profiles dominate symmetric ones in terms of social efficiency. In this article, we are motivated by economic settings where the set of potential participants is dispersed, and it is not possible to achieve the ex ante co-ordination required for asymmetric equilibria.
One possible remedy could then be that the seller approaches only a subset of potential bidders and restricts participation to them only. Since the seller does not know the private information of the potential bidders, it is not clear if such a strategy would raise the expected revenues. Moreover, if only a small fraction of all potentially interested bidders are truly interested and if the seller incurs a cost of contacting the bidders, it is clearly better to rely on self-selecting mechanisms of the type that we analyse in this article.
The seller might also choose a limited form of disclosure and disclose some statistical information on the number of participants. In our current setting, no disclosure is often optimal, but in richer settings with e.g. incomplete information on the participation costs, such disclosures might be valuable to the seller.
6.4 Affiliated private values
Our analysis can be extended to cover affiliated private values models as well. Matthews (1987) analyses the effect of disclosing the number of bidders in a first-price auction. He assumes that best responses in the informal auction are monotone in signals, and that the bids in the formal auction are increasing in the number of participants. Under these assumptions, he demonstrates the payoff superiority of the informal auction.23
For private values models, second-price auction is the pivot mechanism, and as a consequence bidders collect their marginal contribution to the social welfare in the bidding stage. This means that the ex ante participation decisions coincide with the solution to a social planner’s problem when restricted to symmetric entry profiles. Since bidders’ rent is dissipated at the entry stage, the auctioneer collects the entire social surplus in revenues.
Jehiel and Lamy (2015) consider endogenous entry in a private-values model. They show that with independent values, the Poisson-limit of their finite model (without incumbents) has efficient entry equilibria for both second-price and informal first-price auctions even when potential bidders are asymmetric. They also show that disclosing information prior to entry is beneficial to the seller. Our article shows that with affiliated common values, disclosing information after entry decisions have been made may hurt the seller.
APPENDIX
A. Omitted Proofs
Proof of Proposition 1
Proof of Lemma 1
As observed by Pesendorfer and Swinkels (1997) in Lemma 7, winning at a pooling bid p submitted only by high-type bidders comes with a winner’s curse making an upward deviation profitable.
To rule out other types of pooling bids, we note first that there cannot be pooling at any . This is because for such a low bid, for and a deviation to a slightly higher price would be profitable. For , . By affiliation, is increasing in m. Therefore, if type gets an expected payoff of c by bidding , then type gets strictly more than c at the same bid. This is not compatible with interim entry equilibrium.
Since it is not possible to have pooling bids that are made only by high types, pooling is not possible for any either.24 ▪
Proof of Lemma 2
If is an equilibrium of the reduced model (i.e. the model with ), then types and get the same payoff in the full model under strategy profile and hence their behaviour remains consistent with equilibrium. We have to prove that no other type has a strict incentive to enter against . Denote by and the expected payoff of a bidder who bids p against , conditional on state and , respectively. Suppose that there is a type , and a bid such that gets strictly more than c when the others follow . This means that . But since , then either or , implying that either type or would get a payoff strictly greater than c by following bidding strategy . This contradicts the fact that is an equilibrium of the reduced model.
Proof of Lemma 3
Let and denote the bid distributions of an atomless bidding equilibrium b corresponding to entry profile and let , , . We start by ruling out the possibility of gaps in the union of the bid supports. This is by a standard argument: suppose that there is some interval such that no type bids within that interval, but is in the bid support for type θ. Then type θ could reduce her bid from without decreasing her winning probability and this would strictly increase her expected payoff. It follows that:
Note that this does not rule out gaps in the bid supports of individual types.
We next investigate the possible configurations of the bid supports and . We first specify the range of bids where the supports may overlap, i.e. where both types can potentially be indifferent simultaneously. Denote by the payoff of type θ who bids p, when bidding distributions are given by :
Differentiating with respect to p, we have:
In equilibrium, requires to maintain indifference within bidding support. To analyse when this can hold, we denote the two terms in square brackets by and :
These terms are weighted in (9) by positive terms that depend on θ only through . Since , we note that puts more weight on term than , relative to . It is immediate that for and to be zero simultaneously, it must be that . Since and , this is possible only if
This can hold only for low values of p. Let us define as the cutoff value such that the above inequality holds for :
(Note that we define if indifference is never possible). We summarize the implications of this reasoning in the following claim. Part 1 says that the overlap of bidding supports is possible only for . Part 2 says that in any range where only low type randomizes, value of high type is U-shaped with minimum at . Part 3 says that in any range where only high type randomizes, value of low type is decreasing and hence the low type prefers lower bids.
Let and be given, and let , , be an atomless equilibrium bidding distribution. We have:
- (1)
If for , then .
- (2)If and , then
- (3)
If and , then .
Part 1: for requires that , which is only possible if . Part 2: If , then . If , then implies that for , and for . Since , the result follows. Part 3: If , then . If , then implies that . Since , the result follows. ▪
We show next that if
then the bid supports of the two types cannot overlap. Suppose to the contrary that the supports do overlap. By Part 1 of Claim 2, overlap is possible only for , and combining this with Part 2 we must have whenever the supports overlap. As before, we denote by the upper bound of the bid support of low types, i.e. . Since there are no gaps in the union of the bid supports, we also have . Both types must then be indifferent between bidding 0 and , which gives the following indifference condition:
for . This can be rewritten as
For this to hold simultaneously for both types , both of the two terms in square brackets must be zero. Suppose that the second term is zero, that is
Multiplying by , this is equivalent to
Combining this with (10) and using the fact that , this implies that
and so multiplying by we see that the first term in square brackets in (11) is strictly positive:
This is a contradiction. We can conclude that it is not possible to make both types indifferent between bidding 0 and , and so the bid supports must be non-overlapping intervals with a single point in common.
We show next that if
then the bid supports must overlap. Suppose to the contrary that there is an equilibrium, where the bid-supports are non-overlapping intervals: and for some . The low type must be indifferent between bidding 0 and :
which can be rewritten as
For this to hold, one of the terms in square brackets must be positive and the other one must be negative. Combining this with (12), we must have
But then, since , this implies that
or
and so the high type has a strictly profitable deviation to bidding 0 rather than . We can conclude that an equilibrium with non-overlapping intervals is not possible. The only possibility is an equilibrium with overlapping bid supports, and as we have already concluded above, in such a case 0 must be contained in the supports of both types. ▪
Proof of Lemma 4
Proof of Proposition 2


Proof of Lemma 5
Suppose that there is an equilibrium with for some . Let , , denote the ex ante equilibrium payoff conditional on state for bidding according to type strategy. Since breaks just even in equilibrium, . We have . Hence, if , then type can get strictly more than c by mimicking the bidding strategy of type , and if , then type can get strictly more than c by mimicking the bidding strategy of type . Therefore, it must be that . This of course means that any type can get c by mimicking type bidding strategy. It remains to show that some type gets strictly more by deviating from type bidding strategy.
Since we consider formal auctions, the bidding strategy is conditional on n, the realized number of entrants. Let denote the expected payoff of bidding p, conditional on n and conditional on ω. Suppose that there is some n and either some interval or an atom in the support of type bidding strategy such that within or at . Then, either type or type gets in expectation more than by deviating to or for this n. By using this deviation for n, and by mimicking for all other n, this type (either or ) gets a strictly higher ex ante payoff than , contradicting the assumption that this strategy is an equilibrium in the overall game with interim entry. It follows that unless within the whole support of type for all n, there cannot exist an equilibrium with , .
It remains to show that we cannot have within the whole support of type for all n. First, note that for any , supp , where is the bidding distribution of type i for realized number of entrants n. If this were not the case, then anyone bidding would have a strictly profitable deviation up (recall that , so if there is no atom at , then one can never win by bidding there, and if there is an atom, a small deviation increases probability of winning discretely). But for all , we always have , and hence . ▪
Proof of Proposition 3
Assume that only the highest and lowest types, h and l, enter with a strictly positive rate. Let denote the expected payoff of type θ in the formal auction with entry profile . We proceed to show that there is an entry profile satisfying . It is clear that in that case an intermediate type could not get more than c by entering. To see this, suppose to the contrary that , but type gets strictly more than c using bidding strategy against . Let denote the ex ante payoff conditional on state ω using bidding strategy . If , then type h would get strictly more than c using , a contradiction. Similarly, if , then type l would get strictly more than c using , a contradiction.
The result now follows from the intermediate value theorem: there must be some such that . Setting , we have . Coupled with the bidding equilibrium characterized in Lemma 6, this is an equilibrium. Since the reaction curve is strictly decreasing in , the entry rates satisfy , . ▪
Proof of Proposition 4
Proof of Proposition 5
As a first step, we show that with a given entry profile , a high type gets a strictly higher payoff in the formal auction than in the informal auction if is small enough.
If zero is in the bidding support of both types in the informal auction, the result is immediate. Therefore, assume that there is no overlap in the bidding supports in the informal auction and denote by the common point in the two supports.
Consider the following bidding strategies to compare the informal auction and the formal auction. In the informal auction, let both types bid . Since this is in the support of both types, it generates the equilibrium payoff to both types. In the formal auction, let both types bid , where is small. Since we can take arbitrarily close to zero, we calculate the winning probability and expected payoffs in the limit as . With this strategy, a bidder wins if and only if there are no (other) high type bidders, and the price in such a case is either zero or . Clearly, this strategy gives the equilibrium payoff for both types (in the limit as ). Given these strategies, the player gets the same allocation in both auction formats (i.e. gets the object if and only if there are no high types present), and therefore we may compare the players’ payoffs across the auction formats by contrasting their expected payments conditional on winning.
The second step is just to conclude that changing the auction format from the informal one to the formal one will increase distortion. Fixing the equilibrium entry profile of the informal auction, but changing the auction format to the formal auction, a high type bidder gets in the bidding equilibrium strictly more than c. To compensate this, the high-type entry rate in an equilibrium to the formal auction must satisfy . Since in both auction formats , the formal auction hence moves the equilibrium entry profile along further away from the social optimum than the informal auction. By Lemma 4, the total surplus is then higher in the informal auction than in the formal auction. ▪
Proof of Proposition 6
The plan of this proof is to fix the entry profile to be socially optimal, i.e. , and show that there is a pair and for which the associated bidding equilibrium gives expected payoff of c to both types of entrants. Noting further that no type other than h or l would make strictly more than c, this gives the desired result. We will proceed in sequence with the formal and informal auction formats, followed by the argument for posted prices.
Formal auction:
By Proposition 2, the equilibrium entry profile is inefficient in the formal auction if and only if . Assume that , but fix the entry profile to be efficient: . Since we have assumed , this satisfies and .
Let us now equip the auction with a positive entry fee and a negative minimum bid . Since we keep the entry profile fixed, the entry fee f has no effect on the bidding equilibrium, and the minimum bid is only binding for . Lemma 6 continues to hold with an obvious modification: if , the only participant bids (instead of zero). This bidding equilibrium is unique. Given this pair , we denote by and the values of the high and low type entrant, respectively, in the unique bidding equilibrium with fixed entry profile .
If the seller is to post a price p and an entry fee f, she can extract full social surplus in the model. To see this, let and be the conditional probabilities of conditional on signal respectively.
Denote by and the values of the two types in the unique bidding equilibrium with entry profile , entry fee f, and minimum bid , where . By the properties of the bidding equilibrium, these must be continuous in for . Since entry fee has no effect on bidding, , .
We conclude therefore that in order to induce efficient participation, the seller must post a negative price and extract the buyer surplus in strictly positive participation fees. ▪
Acknowledgments
We would like to thank Alp Atakan, Chang-Koo Chi, Mehmet Ekmekci, Daniel Hauser, Kyungmin Kim, Stephan Lauermann, Matti Liski, Julia Salmi, Andrea Speit, Hannu Vartiainen, the editor Andrea Galeotti, four referees, and numerous seminar audiences for helpful comments on the article. This project has received financial support from the Research Council of Finland (Decision: 325218).
Supplementary Data
Supplementary data are available at Review of Economic Studies online.
References
Footnotes
We use this terminology for the ease of exposition only. Other authors, in particular DeMarzo et al. (2005) use ‘informal auctions’ to indicate lack of commitment to the auction mechanism.
The possible reversal of the linkage principle of Milgrom and Weber (1982) in informal auctions was observed by Matthews (1987) in an affiliated private values auction with the same exogenous distribution of bidders across the different auction formats.
This is a common assumption in the literature used in e.g. Lauermann and Speit (2023), Lauermann and Wolinsky (2017), and Atakan and Ekmekci (2021). Generalizing the analysis to more general state spaces is an open question.
In the matching market application analysed in the Supplementary Appendix, this finding translates into some bidders purposefully targeting sellers with a low expected quality.
Landsberger (2007) is an early paper showing that existence of monotone equilibria often fails in auctions with participation costs.
Neither uniqueness nor existence is obvious from the outset in informal auctions. Lauermann and Wolinsky (2017) discuss multiplicity of equilibria due to atoms in bidding distributions in their model of first-price auction with an unknown number of bidders. Lauermann and Speit (2023) show that a first-price auction with an exogenously given probability distribution for the number of participants may even fail to have an equilibrium.
In the model with endogenous choice between different procurement auctions, high opportunity cost of choosing a particular auction would result from a relatively small number of suppliers in the market.
The seller would have an incentive to submit a shill bid equal to her valuation for the object.
The equilibrium determination of information accuracy in common values auctions started with Matthews (1977, 1984). Persico (2000) extended this line of research to revenue comparisons for different auction formats. Since the number of bidders and equilibrium information acquisition decisions are deterministic, equilibrium bidding in these papers is still as in standard affiliated auctions models.
Pinkse and Tan (2005) have shown that the monotonicity in the number of bidders in the formal auction can be problematic.
We comment on possible interpretations of this common participation cost at the end of this section.
We could alternatively derive the Poisson entry model as a limit of large finite models. For a discussion of such a model in the context of a procurement auction with private values, see Jehiel and Lamy (2015).
We show below that ties cannot happen with positive probability in informal auctions.
We analyse this market as an urn-ball model where the distribution of number of buyers bidding on a given seller’s product follows a Poisson distribution with endogenously determined parameters. The resulting bidding stage is equivalent to our main model.
We say that entry is monotone, if for all .
If , then entry is desirable only in the high state. As a result, the planner would never induce entry by types other than , and optimal entry would be monotone.
We thank Andrea Speit for pointing this out to us.
This is true also in the formal auction, where the low type gets rewarded if and only if no other bidder is present. We characterize the bidding equilibrium for that case in Lemma 6 below.
With only one entering type, the bidding equilibrium in an informal auction is a connected interval containing zero. In the formal auction, a bidder bids zero if no other bidder is present and otherwise bids the expected value of the object conditional on the number of entering bidders.
Note that this strategy is almost a best-response to both types of bidders and therefore allows meaningful comparison between expected payments across the signals even though it is not within equilibrium support for the low type bidders. In the limit as , types are indifferent between bidding and . The only effect of deviating up by is that this will tilt the rationing to the deviator in case of a tie at .
In a model with two potential bidders, this is always the case.
Even though the assumptions seem natural, Pinkse and Tan (2005) have shown that monotonicity in the number of participants does not always hold. Similarly, monotonicity in signals can also be problematic in the informal auction and this can lead to existence problems in models with an exogenous random number of bidders as shown in Lauermann and Speit (2023).
Note that this argument applies also in the case with a finite number of bidders.
Author notes
The editor in charge of this paper was Andrea Galeotti